Foto dell'autore
6 opere 32 membri 1 recensione

Sull'Autore

Carlos R. Bovell is a graduate of Westminster Theological Seminary and the Institute for Christian Studies, Toronto. His other books include Inerrancy and the Spiritual Formation of Younger Evangelicals, By Good and Necessary Consequence: A Preliminary Genealogy of Biblicist Foundationalism, and mostra altro Rehabilitating Inerrancy in a Culture of Fear. mostra meno

Opere di Carlos R. Bovell

Etichette

Informazioni generali

Sesso
male

Utenti

Recensioni

11-12/14 B&C review

For Temple, this "faux-pas" was the belief that philosophical inquiry, to be successful, should proceed according to a geometric or axiomatic model: begin with indisputable truths or axioms ("I think, therefore I am"), and from there engage in airtight logical reasoning to establish further truths—which, prior to their establishment, may have been highly disputed—such as the existence of God and the immortality of the soul. second paragraph

The clause in question comes from the sixth article in the Confession, and at the beginning of his book Bovell displays it immediately below a similar statement taken from Descartes' Discourse on Method (bold and italics due to Bovell in both cases): sixth para

The second part reads, "Nevertheless, we acknowledge the inward illumination of the Spirit of God to be necessary for the saving understanding of such things as are revealed in the Word: and that there are some circumstances concerning the worship of God, and government of the Church, common to human actions and societies, which are to be ordered by the light of nature, and Christian prudence, according to the general rules of the Word, which are always to be observed." thirteenth

RUSSELL W. HOWELL
Inerrancy: A Cartesian Faux-Pas?
"By good and necessary consequence."

"If I were asked what was the most disastrous moment in the history of Europe I should be strongly tempted to answer that it was that period of leisure when René Descartes, having no claims to meet, remained for a whole day 'shut up alone in a stove.' " So wrote the normally diplomatic William Temple in chapter three of his Nature, Man, and God, originally given as a series of Gifford Lectures, and published in 1934.

Temple delivered his talks while serving as Archbishop of York, and chose for that chapter the less than diplomatic title "The Cartesian Faux-Pas." For Temple, this "faux-pas" was the belief that philosophical inquiry, to be successful, should proceed according to a geometric or axiomatic model: begin with indisputable truths or axioms ("I think, therefore I am"), and from there engage in airtight logical reasoning to establish further truths—which, prior to their establishment, may have been highly disputed—such as the existence of God and the immortality of the soul. Indeed, in the synopsis to his Meditations, Descartes states, "[I]t was my aim to write nothing of which I could not give exact demonstration, and that I therefore felt myself obliged to adopt an order similar to that in use among the geometers, viz., to premise all upon which the proposition in question depends, before coming to any conclusion respecting it."

Temple thought that Descartes' strategy ("Let's pretend I don't exist and see if I can prove that I do") was a violation of common sense, and dismissed the idea that the success of the axiomatic method in mathematics could be extended to philosophy. Furthermore, he claimed that the method produced disastrous results "not only in philosophy, but also in politics and economics, with all that this means for human happiness or misery."

Carlos Bovell, in his By Good and Necessary Consequence: A Preliminary Genealogy of Biblicist Foundationalism, extends a form of Temple's thinking and argues that an axiomatic methodological mindset led to a disastrous result in theology: a clause in the Westminster Confession. For Bovell, the approach to biblical interpretation governed by this clause has resulted in the shattered faiths of many young evangelicals. It is a shattering that predictably results from an inability to come to terms with scriptural data when combined with a hermeneutic guided by a Cartesian deductivist methodology. In particular, it germinates from a belief in the inerrancy of Scripture.

The clause in question comes from the sixth article in the Confession, and at the beginning of his book Bovell displays it immediately below a similar statement taken from Descartes' Discourse on Method (bold and italics due to Bovell in both cases):

Concerning objects proposed for study, we ought to investigate what we can clearly and evidently intuit or deduce with certainty, and not what other people have thought or whatever we ourselves conjecture. For knowledge can be obtained in no other way. (Descartes, 1637)
The whole counsel of God concerning all things necessary for His own glory, man's salvation, faith and life, is either expressly set down in Scripture, or by good and necessary consequence may be deduced from Scripture: unto which nothing at any time is to be added, whether by new revelations of the Spirit or traditions of men. (Westminster Confession, 1646)
The two quotations bear a striking resemblance, especially as Bovell lays them out. To reinforce the connection between them, he orchestrates a nifty survey highlighting the development of deductive thinking that reaches a crescendo in the 17th century. The survey, which makes up more than half of his book, begins with the Pythagorean school of 500 BC.

In rehearsing the ideas of Pythagoras, Bovell is careful to point out that caution must be taken when consulting second-hand sources. Iamblichus (c. AD 300), who wrote extensively on Pythagoras, is often accused of projecting the methodological approach of his day back to the time of Pythagoras. One almost has to go back to Aristotle (c. 350 BC) to gain some confidence in the reliability of any attestations. Still, secondary sources can be useful, and those who are interested in the development of logic will find Bovell's presentation informative. To illustrate, Pythagoras and Thales (as attested by Proclus) were the first to exhibit an argument that generalizes, that is, one that holds true for a whole range of cases and not just a particular example.

Continuing his account, Bovell examines the development of deduction and dialectic in Plato's work (c. 400 BC). Where the Pythagoreans saw music as a "doorway to mathematics," Plato focused on mathematics as a doorway to knowledge. In assessing Plato's work, Bovell draws from portions in the Meno, Phaedo, and the Republic. In doing so he cites a variety of sources that indicate a growing favor on Plato's part for theoretical arguments over empirical evidence. Yet Plato was not so enchanted with deduction as were the Pythagoreans. He favored a dialectical style, as it better enabled him to re-examine initial hypotheses. Further progress in deduction would have to wait until someone could produce a refined theory of axiomatics. Aristotle's Posterior Analytics fit the bill, but Bovell points out that even there Aristotle's method amounted to a merging of the ideas of Pythagoras and Plato, not necessarily a strict deductivism.

From Aristotle the survey continues over the next several chapters by examining Euclid's Elements (c. 300 BC), Proclus' deductive metaphysics (c. AD 400), Boethius' use of axiomatics (c. AD 500), and Aquinas' commentary on Boethius (c. AD 1250). In each case Bovell provides an extensive analysis, and his bibliography of over 400 items provides ample fodder for investigating some of his more provocative conclusions. He states, for example, that the rigor of Aristotle's axiomatics served "anagogical rather than epistemological" ends, and that the axioms the Greeks used for doing their mathematical work were chosen not because of "self-evident truth and unprovability. They are rather theoretical and practical permission to take a specific direction of thought, an expository tour of the discipline in question." In particular, Euclid's axioms are validated because they lead to a well-known and accepted result: the Pythagorean theorem. Doing so helps "confirm the hypotheses [i.e., the axioms] listed at the beginning of Book I [of the Elements]."

While most mathematicians would agree that axioms (from the Greek axios, meaning worthy) are chosen in part because they enable the construction of a useful system, they might well judge it a stretch to argue that the Greeks had only that end in mind and were not concerned with epistemology. Euclid's proof of the Pythagorean Theorem is the 47th proposition out of a total of 467 spread across 13 books. A substantial number of those propositions are not at all obvious to the point that their proof would justify the axioms in Book I. Rather, their conclusions are justified precisely because of the trustworthiness of the axioms.

Mathematicians might also take issue with Bovell on some smaller points. For example, he illustrates the (Pythagorean) idea of generalization with a particular case. He begins with the (true) inequality that 6 > 5, then multiplies both numbers by -1 to get -6 and -5. What relation do they now bear to one other? Obviously, -6 -b, thus proving (for arbitrary numbers) that multiplying by minus one reverses the inequality. Okay, but why begin by supposing that -x b, and then concluding that -x
… (altro)
 
Segnalato
keithhamblen | Dec 1, 2014 |

Statistiche

Opere
6
Utenti
32
Popolarità
#430,838
Voto
3.0
Recensioni
1
ISBN
12