Pagina principaleGruppiConversazioniAltroStatistiche
Cerca nel Sito
Questo sito utilizza i cookies per fornire i nostri servizi, per migliorare le prestazioni, per analisi, e (per gli utenti che accedono senza fare login) per la pubblicità. Usando LibraryThing confermi di aver letto e capito le nostre condizioni di servizio e la politica sulla privacy. Il tuo uso del sito e dei servizi è soggetto a tali politiche e condizioni.

Risultati da Google Ricerca Libri

Fai clic su di un'immagine per andare a Google Ricerca Libri.

Sto caricando le informazioni...

Epicureanism

di Tim O'Keefe

UtentiRecensioniPopolaritàMedia votiCitazioni
522498,500 (4.29)1
Epicureanism was one of the major philosophical systems of the Hellenistic world. It provided a systematic account of the nature of the world and our place in it, how we can come to know the world, and how we can attain happiness. Founded by Epicurus of Samos (c.341-270 BCE) the Epicurean school of philosophy flourished for hundreds of years after Epicurus? death, and its rediscovery helped shape the scientific revolution. This clear and engaging introduction provides lucid exposition of the central tenets of Epicurus? philosophy. Part 1 of the book examines the fundamentals of Epicurus? metaphysics, including atoms, cosmology, mechanistic biology, the nature and functioning of the mind, and death. Part 2 explores Epicurus? epistemology, including his arguments against scepticism and his ideas on sensations, preconceptions and feelings. The third and final part deals with Epicurus? ethics, exploring his arguments for hedonism, his distinctive conceptions of types of pleasure and desire, his belief in virtue, and his notions of justice and friendship. Tim O?Keefe explores the arguments supporting Epicurus? positions, indicating their strengths and weaknesses, while showing how they connect to other parts of his philosophy and how Epicureanism hangs together as a whole. Particular stress is placed on those features that have enduring philosophical interest and which parallel debates in contemporary philosophy. O?Keefe shows Epicurus to be a philosopher of the highest order and that even after two millennia grappling with his ideas continues to reward study.… (altro)
Nessuno
Sto caricando le informazioni...

Iscriviti per consentire a LibraryThing di scoprire se ti piacerà questo libro.

Attualmente non vi sono conversazioni su questo libro.

» Vedi 1 citazione

Mostra 2 di 2


If you were introduced to ancient Greek philosophy in college, you probably were given a few dialogues of Plato and some selections of Aristotle to read and discuss in class. If the dramatized logic of Plato didn't turn you off completely from philosophy, then the convoluted, dry, uninspiring words of Aristotle probably did the trick. In all likelihood, Epicurus was not even mentioned. Fortunately for us, we now have Epicureanism by Tim O'Keefe, a clear, easy-to-read yet in-depth presentation of each aspect of the philosophy of Epicurus: his physics and metaphysics, epistemology, and ethics, complete with many scholarly references.

O'Keefe writes in the introductory chapter "Plato and Epicurus are opposed on almost every important matter; as a first approximation, one will not go far wrong in viewing Epicurus as the anti-Plato." If this sound like a completely different way of pursuing philosophy than you were taught in college, you are absolutely correct. O'Keefe continues, "Epicurus holds that the most pleasant life is a tranquil one, free of fear and need." I only wish my boyhood environment and schooling emphasized tranquility, joy and freedom from fear and craving, rather than regimentation, mindless competition, and forced conformity. But, it is not too late for any of us. We can learn from Epicurus and O'Keefe's book is an excellent place to start.

In the chapter on Cosmology, O'Keefe notes, "Against most other cosmologists, they (the Epicureans) maintain that our world is only one of an infinite number of worlds coming to be and falling apart in a spatially infinite universe that has existed and will exist forever." And further on, "Our particular limited cosmos is only one of an infinite number of cosmoi (the plural of cosmos), each of which comes into existence and will eventually fall apart. But the universe as a whole has no beginning and no end; it has always existed and will always exist. And spatially, the universe stretches infinitely in all directions." Not too bad for philosophers living over two thousand years before the advent of modern physics and astronomy.

Of course, one of the biggest knocks against Epicurus, both during his own lifetime and continuing right up to our present day, is his equating the ultimate good with pleasure. But, as O'Keefe points out, Epicurus had a much refined and qualified concept of pleasure. We read: "Epicurean hedonism is an enlightened hedonism, which recognizes that one must be brave, temperate and wise in order to live pleasantly. But Epicurus is unusual in insisting that the virtues are only instrumental goods, good only for the sake of the pleasure they produce, instead of being good for their own sake. Likewise, philosophy itself is needed to attain pleasure, but has no intrinsic value." Let's be honest: Who of you reading this doesn't value and seek pleasure in life, even if your pleasure is the intellectual pleasure of reading philosophy or literature?

Toward the end of the book, O'Keefe writes, "The Epicureans are convinced that Epicurus is not merely the discoverer of many interesting and cogent arguments. Instead, he is the savior of humanity, and the only route to salvation from superstitious fears and empty desires is by fully accepting his message." To what degree is this applicable and true for our lives today? To explore this question and others, please read O'Keefe's work on Epicureanism. It will be, I can assure you, a most rewarding philosophical journey. ( )
  Glenn_Russell | Nov 13, 2018 |


If you were introduced to ancient Greek philosophy in college, you probably were given a few dialogues of Plato and some selections of Aristotle to read and discuss in class. If the dramatized logic of Plato didn't turn you off completely from philosophy, then the convoluted, dry, uninspiring words of Aristotle probably did the trick. In all likelihood, Epicurus was not even mentioned. Fortunately for us, we now have Epicureanism by Tim O'Keefe, a clear, easy-to-read yet in-depth presentation of each aspect of the philosophy of Epicurus: his physics and metaphysics, epistemology, and ethics, complete with many scholarly references.

O'Keefe writes in the introductory chapter "Plato and Epicurus are opposed on almost every important matter; as a first approximation, one will not go far wrong in viewing Epicurus as the anti-Plato." If this sound like a completely different way of pursuing philosophy than you were taught in college, you are absolutely correct. O'Keefe continues, "Epicurus holds that the most pleasant life is a tranquil one, free of fear and need." I only wish my boyhood environment and schooling emphasized tranquility, joy and freedom from fear and craving, rather than regimentation, mindless competition, and forced conformity. But, it is not too late for any of us. We can learn from Epicurus and O'Keefe's book is an excellent place to start.

In the chapter on Cosmology, O'Keefe notes, "Against most other cosmologists, they (the Epicureans) maintain that our world is only one of an infinite number of worlds coming to be and falling apart in a spatially infinite universe that has existed and will exist forever." And further on, "Our particular limited cosmos is only one of an infinite number of cosmoi (the plural of cosmos), each of which comes into existence and will eventually fall apart. But the universe as a whole has no beginning and no end; it has always existed and will always exist. And spatially, the universe stretches infinitely in all directions." Not too bad for philosophers living over two thousand years before the advent of modern physics and astronomy.

Of course, one of the biggest knocks against Epicurus, both during his own lifetime and continuing right up to our present day, is his equating the ultimate good with pleasure. But, as O'Keefe points out, Epicurus had a much refined and qualified concept of pleasure. We read: "Epicurean hedonism is an enlightened hedonism, which recognizes that one must be brave, temperate and wise in order to live pleasantly. But Epicurus is unusual in insisting that the virtues are only instrumental goods, good only for the sake of the pleasure they produce, instead of being good for their own sake. Likewise, philosophy itself is needed to attain pleasure, but has no intrinsic value." Let's be honest: Who of you reading this doesn't value and seek pleasure in life, even if your pleasure is the intellectual pleasure of reading philosophy or literature?

Toward the end of the book, O'Keefe writes, "The Epicureans are convinced that Epicurus is not merely the discoverer of many interesting and cogent arguments. Instead, he is the savior of humanity, and the only route to salvation from superstitious fears and empty desires is by fully accepting his message." To what degree is this applicable and true for our lives today? To explore this question and others, please read O'Keefe's work on Epicureanism. It will be, I can assure you, a most rewarding philosophical journey. ( )
1 vota GlennRussell | Feb 16, 2017 |
Mostra 2 di 2
nessuna recensione | aggiungi una recensione

Appartiene alle Serie

Devi effettuare l'accesso per contribuire alle Informazioni generali.
Per maggiori spiegazioni, vedi la pagina di aiuto delle informazioni generali.
Titolo canonico
Dati dalle informazioni generali inglesi. Modifica per tradurlo nella tua lingua.
Titolo originale
Titoli alternativi
Data della prima edizione
Personaggi
Luoghi significativi
Eventi significativi
Film correlati
Epigrafe
Dedica
Incipit
Citazioni
Ultime parole
Nota di disambiguazione
Redattore editoriale
Elogi
Lingua originale
DDC/MDS Canonico
LCC canonico

Risorse esterne che parlano di questo libro

Wikipedia in inglese (1)

Epicureanism was one of the major philosophical systems of the Hellenistic world. It provided a systematic account of the nature of the world and our place in it, how we can come to know the world, and how we can attain happiness. Founded by Epicurus of Samos (c.341-270 BCE) the Epicurean school of philosophy flourished for hundreds of years after Epicurus? death, and its rediscovery helped shape the scientific revolution. This clear and engaging introduction provides lucid exposition of the central tenets of Epicurus? philosophy. Part 1 of the book examines the fundamentals of Epicurus? metaphysics, including atoms, cosmology, mechanistic biology, the nature and functioning of the mind, and death. Part 2 explores Epicurus? epistemology, including his arguments against scepticism and his ideas on sensations, preconceptions and feelings. The third and final part deals with Epicurus? ethics, exploring his arguments for hedonism, his distinctive conceptions of types of pleasure and desire, his belief in virtue, and his notions of justice and friendship. Tim O?Keefe explores the arguments supporting Epicurus? positions, indicating their strengths and weaknesses, while showing how they connect to other parts of his philosophy and how Epicureanism hangs together as a whole. Particular stress is placed on those features that have enduring philosophical interest and which parallel debates in contemporary philosophy. O?Keefe shows Epicurus to be a philosopher of the highest order and that even after two millennia grappling with his ideas continues to reward study.

Non sono state trovate descrizioni di biblioteche

Descrizione del libro
Riassunto haiku

Discussioni correnti

Nessuno

Copertine popolari

Link rapidi

Voto

Media: (4.29)
0.5
1
1.5
2
2.5
3
3.5 2
4 2
4.5
5 3

Sei tu?

Diventa un autore di LibraryThing.

 

A proposito di | Contatto | LibraryThing.com | Privacy/Condizioni d'uso | Guida/FAQ | Blog | Negozio | APIs | TinyCat | Biblioteche di personaggi celebri | Recensori in anteprima | Informazioni generali | 206,302,853 libri! | Barra superiore: Sempre visibile